7
Faith and Force: The Destroyers of the Modern
World
1960
(A lecture delivered at Yale University on
February 17, 1960; at Brooklyn College on April 4, 1960; and at
Columbia University on May 5, 1960.)
If you want me to name in one sentence what is
wrong with the modern world, I will say that never before has the
world been clamoring so desperately for answers to crucial
problems—and never before has the world been so frantically
committed to the belief that no answers are possible.
Observe the peculiar nature of this contradiction
and the peculiar emotional atmosphere of our age. There have been
periods in history when men failed to find answers because they
evaded the existence of the problems, pretended that nothing
threatened them and denounced anyone who spoke of approaching
disaster. This is not the predominant attitude of our age. Today,
the voices proclaiming disaster are so fashionable a bromide that
people are battered into apathy by their monotonous insistence; but
the anxiety under that apathy is real. Consciously or
subconsciously, intellectually or emotionally, most people today
know that the world is in a terrible state and that it cannot
continue on its present course much longer.
The existence of the problems is acknowledged, yet
we hear nothing but meaningless generalities and shameful evasions
from our so-called intellectual leaders. Wherever you look—whether
in philosophical publications, or intellectual magazines, or
newspaper editorials or political speeches of either party—you find
the same mental attitude, made of two characteristics: staleness
and superficiality. People seem to insist on talking—and on
carefully saying nothing. The eva-siveness, the dullness, the gray
conformity of today’s intellectual expressions sound like the
voices of men under censorship—where no censorship exists. Never
before has there been an age characterized by such a grotesque
combination of qualities as despair and
boredom.
You might say that this is the honest exhaustion of
men who have done their best in the struggle to find answers, and
have failed. But the dignity of an honestly helpless resignation is
certainly not the emotional atmosphere of our age. An honest
resignation would not be served or expressed by repeating the same
worn-out bromides over and over again, while going through the
motions of a quest. A man who is honestly convinced that he can
find no answers, would not feel the need to pretend that he is
looking for them.
You might say that the explanation lies in our
modern cynicism and that people fail to find answers because they
really don’t care. It is true that people are cynical today, but
this is merely a symptom, not a cause. Today’s cynicism has a
special twist: we are dealing with cynics who do care—and
the ugly secret of our age lies in that which they do care about,
that which they are seeking.
The truth about the intellectual state of the
modern world, the characteristic peculiar to the twentieth century,
which distinguishes it from other periods of cultural crises, is
the fact that what people are seeking is not the answers to
problems, but the reassurance that no answers are
possible.
A friend of mine once said that today’s attitude,
paraphrasing the Bible, is: “Forgive me, Father, for I know not
what I’m doing—and please don’t tell me.”
Observe how noisily the modern intellectuals are
seeking solutions for problems—and how swiftly they blank out the
existence of any theory or idea, past or present, that offers the
lead to a solution. Observe that these modern relativists—with
their credo of intellectual tolerance, of the open mind, of the
anti-absolute—turn into howling dogmatists to denounce anyone who
claims to possess knowledge. Observe that they tolerate anything,
except certainty—and approve of anything, except values. Observe
that they profess to love mankind, and drool with sympathy over any
literary study of murderers, dipsomaniacs, drug addicts and
psychotics, over any presentation of their loved object’s
depravity—and scream with anger when anyone dares to claim that man
is not depraved. Observe that they profess to be moved by
compassion for human suffering—and close their ears indignantly to
any suggestion that man does not have to suffer.
What you see around you today, among modern
intellectuals, is the grotesque spectacle of such attributes as
militant uncertainty, crusading cynicism, dogmatic agnosticism,
boastful self-abasement and self-righteous depravity. The two
absolutes of today’s non-absolutists are that ignorance consists of
claiming knowledge, and that immorality consists of pronouncing
moral judgments.
Now why would people want to cling to the
conviction that doom, darkness, depravity and ultimate disaster are
inevitable? Well, psychologists will tell you that when a man
suffers from neurotic anxiety, he seizes upon any rationalization
available to explain his fear to himself, and he clings to that
rationalization in defiance of logic, reason, reality or any
argument assuring him that the danger can be averted. He does not
want it to be averted because the rationalization serves as
a screen to hide from himself the real cause of his fear, the cause
he does not dare to face.
Ladies and gentlemen, what you are seeing today is
the neurotic anxiety of an entire culture. People do not want to
find any answers to avert their danger: all they want, all they’re
looking for, is only some excuse to yell: “I couldn’t help
it!”
If certain centuries are to be identified by their
dominant characteristics, like the Age of Reason or the Age of
Enlightenment, then ours is the Age of Guilt.
What is it that people dread—and what do they feel
guilty of?
They dread the unadmitted knowledge that their
culture is bankrupt. They feel guilty, because they know that
they have brought it to bankruptcy and that they lack the
courage to make a fresh start.
They dread the knowledge that they have reached the
dead end of the traditional evasions of the centuries behind them,
that the contradictions of Western civilization have caught up with
them, that no compromises or middle-of-the-roads will work any
longer and that the responsibility of resolving those
contradictions by making a fundamental choice is theirs, now,
today. They are temporizing, in order to evade the fact that we
have to check our basic premises, or pay the price of all
unresolved contradictions, which is: destruction.
The three values which men had held for centuries
and which have now collapsed are: mysticism, collectivism,
altruism. Mysticism—as a cultural power—died at the time of the
Renaissance. Collectivism—as a political ideal—died in World War
II. As to altruism—it has never been alive. It is the poison of
death in the blood of Western civilization, and men survived it
only to the extent to which they neither believed nor practiced it.
But it has caught up with them—and that is the killer which
they now have to face and to defeat. That is the basic
choice they have to make. If any civilization is to survive, it is
the morality of altruism that men have to reject.
Some of you will recognize my next sentences. Yes,
this is an age of moral crisis. Yes, you are bearing
punishment for your evil. Your moral code has reached its climax,
the blind alley at the end of its course. And if you wish to go on
living, what you now need is not to return to morality, but
to discover it.
What is morality? It is a code of values to
guide man’s choices and actions—the choices which determine the
purpose and the course of his life. It is a code by means of
which he judges what is right or wrong, good or evil.
What is the moral code of altruism? The basic
principle of altruism is that man has no right to exist for his own
sake, that service to others is the only justification of his
existence, and that self-sacrifice is his highest moral duty,
virtue and value.
Do not confuse altruism with kindness, good will or
respect for the rights of others. These are not primaries, but
consequences, which, in fact, altruism makes impossible. The
irreducible primary of altruism, the basic absolute, is
self-sacrifice—which means: self-immolation,
self-abnegation, self-denial, self-destruction—which means: the
self as a standard of evil, the selfless as a
standard of the good.
Do not hide behind such superficialities as whether
you should or should not give a dime to a beggar. That is not the
issue. The issue is whether you do or do not have the
right to exist without giving him that dime. The issue is
whether you must keep buying your life, dime by dime, from any
beggar who might choose to approach you. The issue is whether the
need of others is the first mortgage on your life and the moral
purpose of your existence. The issue is whether man is to be
regarded as a sacrificial animal. Any man of self-esteem will
answer: “No.” Altruism says: “Yes.”
Now there is one word—a single word—which can blast
the morality of altruism out of existence and which it cannot
withstand—the word: “Why?” Why must man live for the sake of
others? Why must he be a sacrificial animal? Why is
that the good? There is no earthly reason for it—and, ladies and
gentlemen, in the whole history of philosophy no earthly
reason has ever been given.
It is only mysticism that can permit
moralists to get away with it. It was mysticism, the
unearthly, the supernatural, the irrational that has always
been called upon to justify it—or, to be exact, to escape the
necessity of justification. One does not justify the irrational,
one just takes it on faith. What most moralists—and few of their
victims—realize is that reason and altruism are incompatible. And
this is the basic contradiction of Western civilization:
reason versus altruism. This is the conflict that had to explode
sooner or later.
The real conflict, of course, is reason versus
mysticism. But if it weren’t for the altruist morality, mysticism
would have died when it did die—at the Renaissance—leaving no
vampire to haunt Western culture. A “vampire” is supposed to be a
dead creature that comes out of its grave only at night—only in the
darkness—and drains the blood of the living. The description,
applied to altruism, is exact.
Western civilization was the child and product of
reason—via ancient Greece. In all other civilizations, reason has
always been the menial servant—the handmaiden—of mysticism. You may
observe the results. It is only Western culture that has ever been
dominated—imperfectly, incompletely, precariously and at rare
intervals—but still, dominated by reason. You may observe the
results of that.
The conflict of reason versus mysticism is the
issue of life or death—of freedom or slavery—of progress or
stagnant brutality. Or, to put it another way, it is the conflict
of consciousness versus unconsciousness.
Let us define our terms. What is reason? Reason is
the faculty which perceives, identifies and integrates the material
provided by man’s senses. Reason integrates man’s perceptions by
means of forming abstractions or conceptions, thus raising man’s
knowledge from the perceptual level, which he shares with
animals, to the conceptual level, which he alone can reach.
The method which reason employs in this process is
logic—and logic is the art of non-contradictory
identification.
What is mysticism? Mysticism is the acceptance of
allegations without evidence or proof, either apart from or
against the evidence of one’s senses and one’s reason.
Mysticism is the claim to some non-sensory, non-rational,
non-definable, non-identifiable means of knowledge, such as
“instinct,” “intuition,” “revelation,” or any form of “just
knowing.”
Reason is the perception of reality, and rests on a
single axiom: the Law of Identity.
Mysticism is the claim to the perception of some
other reality—other than the one in which we live— whose definition
is only that it is not natural, it is supernatural, and is
to be perceived by some form of unnatural or supernatural
means.
You realize, of course, that
epistemology—the theory of knowledge—is the most complex
branch of philosophy, which cannot be covered exhaustively in a
single lecture. So I will not attempt to cover it. I will say only
that those who wish a fuller discussion will find it in Atlas
Shrugged. For the purposes of tonight’s discussion, the
definitions I have given you contain the essence of the
issue, regardless of whose theory, argument or philosophy you
choose to accept.
I will repeat: Reason is the faculty which
perceives, identifies and integrates the material provided by man’s
senses. Mysticism is the claim to a non-sensory means of
knowledge.
In Western civilization, the period ruled by
mysticism is known as the Dark Ages and the Middle Ages. I will
assume that you know the nature of that period and the state of
human existence in those ages. The Renaissance broke the rule of
the mystics. “Renais-sance” means “rebirth.” Few people today will
care to remind you that it was a rebirth of reason—of man’s
mind.
In the light of what followed—most particularly, in
the light of the industrial revolution—nobody can now take faith,
or religion, or revelation, or any form of mysticism as his basic
and exclusive guide to existence, not in the way it was taken in
the Middle Ages. This does not mean that the Renaissance has
automatically converted everybody to rationality; far from it. It
means only that so long as a single automobile, a single skyscraper
or a single copy of Aristotle’s Logic remains in existence, nobody
will be able to arouse men’s hope, eagerness and joyous enthusiasm
by telling them to ditch their mind and rely on mystic faith. This
is why I said that mysticism, as a cultural power, is dead. Observe
that in the attempts at a mystic revival today, it is not an appeal
to life, hope and joy that the mystics are making, but an appeal to
fear, doom and despair. “Give up, your mind is impotent, life is
only a foxhole,” is not a motto that can revive a culture.
Now, if you ask me to name the man most responsible
for the present state of the world, the man whose influence has
almost succeeded in destroying the achievements of the
Renaissance—I will name Immanuel Kant. He was the philosopher who
saved the morality of altruism, and who knew that what it had to be
saved from was—reason.
This is not a mere hypothesis. It is a known
historical fact that Kant’s interest and purpose in philosophy was
to save the morality of altruism, which could not survive without a
mystic base. His metaphysics and his epistemology were devised for
that purpose. He did not, of course, announce himself as a
mystic—few of them have, since the Renaissance. He announced
himself as a champion of reason—of “pure” reason.
There are two ways to destroy the power of a
concept: one, by an open attack in open discussion—the other, by
subversion, from the inside; that is: by subverting the meaning of
the concept, setting up a straw man and then refuting it. Kant did
the second. He did not attack reason—he merely constructed such a
version of what is reason that it made mysticism look like
plain, rational common sense by comparison. He did not deny the
validity of reason—he merely claimed that reason is “limited,” that
it leads us to impossible contradictions, that everything we
perceive is an illusion and that we can never perceive reality or
“things as they are.” He claimed, in effect, that the things we
perceive are not real, because we perceive them.
A “straw man” is an odd metaphor to apply to such
an enormous, cumbersome, ponderous construction as Kant’s system of
epistemology. Nevertheless, a straw man is what it was—and the
doubts, the uncertainty, the skepticism that followed, skepticism
about man’s ability ever to know anything, were not, in fact,
applicable to human consciousness, because it was not a human
consciousness that Kant’s robot represented. But philosophers
accepted it as such. And while they cried that reason had been
invalidated, they did not notice that reason had been pushed off
the philosophical scene altogether and that the faculty they were
arguing about was not reason.
No, Kant did not destroy reason; he merely did as
thorough a job of undercutting as anyone could ever do.
If you trace the roots of all our current
philosophies—such as Pragmatism, Logical Positivism, and all the
rest of the neo-mystics who announce happily that you cannot
prove that you exist—you will find that they all grew out of
Kant.
As to Kant’s version of the altruist morality, he
claimed that it was derived from “pure reason,” not from
revelation—except that it rested on a special instinct for
duty, a “categorical imperative” which one “just knows.”
His version of morality makes the Christian one sound like a
healthy, cheerful, benevolent code of selfishness. Christianity
merely told man to love his neighbor as himself; that’s not exactly
rational—but at least it does not forbid man to love himself. What
Kant propounded was full, total, abject selflessness: he held that
an action is moral only if you perform it out of a sense of
duty and derive no benefit from it of any kind, neither material
nor spiritual; if you derive any benefit, your action is not moral
any longer. This is the ultimate form of demanding that man
turn himself into a “shmoo”—the mystic little animal of the Li’l
Abner comic strip, that went around seeking to be eaten by
somebody.
It is Kant’s version of altruism that is generally
accepted today, not practiced—who can practice it?—but guiltily
accepted. It is Kant’s version of altruism that people, who have
never heard of Kant, profess when they equate self-interest with
evil. It is Kant’s version of altruism that’s working whenever
people are afraid to admit the pursuit of any personal pleasure or
gain or motive—whenever men are afraid to confess that they are
seeking their own happiness—whenever businessmen are afraid to say
that they are making profits—whenever the victims of an advancing
dictatorship are afraid to assert their “selfish” rights.
The ultimate monument to Kant and to the whole
altruist morality is Soviet Russia.
If you want to prove to yourself the power of ideas
and, particularly, of morality—the intellectual history of the
nineteenth century would be a good example to study. The greatest,
unprecedented, undreamed of events and achievements were taking
place before men’s eyes—but men did not see them and did not
understand their meaning, as they do not understand it to this day.
I am speaking of the industrial revolution, of the United States
and of capitalism. For the first time in history, men gained
control over physical nature and threw off the control of men over
men—that is: men discovered science and political freedom. The
creative energy, the abundance, the wealth, the rising standard of
living for every level of the population were such that the
nineteenth century looks like a fiction-Utopia, like a blinding
burst of sunlight, in the drab progression of most of human
history. If life on earth is one’s standard of value, then the
nineteenth century moved mankind forward more than all the other
centuries combined.
Did anyone appreciate it? Does anyone appreciate it
now? Has anyone identified the causes of that historical
miracle?
They did not and have not. What blinded them? The
morality of altruism.
Let me explain this. There are, fundamentally, only
two causes of the progress of the nineteenth century—the same two
causes which you will find at the root of any happy, benevolent,
progressive era in human history. One cause is psychological, the
other existential—or: one pertains to man’s consciousness, the
other to the physical conditions of his existence. The first is
reason, the second is freedom. And when I say
“freedom,” I do not mean poetic sloppiness, such as “freedom
from want” or “freedom from fear” or “freedom from the necessity of
earning a living.” I mean “freedom from compulson—freedom
from rule by physical force.” Which means: political
freedom.
These two—reason and freedom—are corollaries, and
their relationship is reciprocal: when men are rational, freedom
wins; when men are free, reason wins.
Their antagonists are: faith and
force. These, also, are corollaries: every period of history
dominated by mysticism, was a period of statism, of dictatorship,
of tyranny. Look at the Middle Ages—and look at the political
systems of today.
The nineteenth century was the ultimate product and
expression of the intellectual trend of the Renaissance and the Age
of Reason, which means: of a predominantly Aristotelian philosophy.
And, for the first time in history, it created a new economic
system, the necessary corollary of political freedom, a system of
free trade on a free market: capitalism.
No, it was not a full, perfect, unregulated,
totally laissez-faire capitalism—as it should have been. Various
degrees of government interference and control still remained, even
in America—and this is what led to the eventual destruction
of capitalism. But the extent to which certain countries were free
was the exact extent of their economic progress. America, the
freest, achieved the most.
Never mind the low wages and the harsh living
conditions of the early years of capitalism. They were all that the
national economies of the time could afford. Capitalism did not
create poverty—it inherited it. Compared to the centuries of
precapitalist starvation, the living conditions of the poor in the
early years of capitalism were the first chance the poor had ever
had to survive. As proof—the enormous growth of the European
population during the nineteenth century, a growth of over 300
percent, as compared to the previous growth of something like 3
percent per century.
Now why was this not appreciated? Why did
capitalism, the truly magnificent benefactor of mankind, arouse
nothing but resentment, denunciations and hatred, then and now? Why
did the so-called defenders of capitalism keep apologizing for it,
then and now? Because, ladies and gentlemen, capitalism and
altruism are incompatible.
Make no mistake about it—and tell it to your
Republican friends: capitalism and altruism cannot coexist in the
same man or in the same society.
Tell it to anyone who attempts to justify
capitalism on the ground of the “public good” or the “general
welfare” or “service to society” or the benefit it brings to the
poor. All these things are true, but they are the by-products, the
secondary consequences of capitalism—not its goal, purpose or moral
justification. The moral justification of capitalism is man’s right
to exist for his own sake, neither sacrificing himself to others
nor sacrificing others to himself; it is the recognition that
man—every man—is an end in himself, not a means to the ends of
others, not a sacrificial animal serving anyone’s need.
This is implicit in the function of capitalism,
but, until now, it has never been stated explicitly, in
moral terms. Why not? Because this is the base of a morality
diametrically opposed to the morality of altruism which, to this
day, people are afraid to challenge.
There is a tragic, twisted sort of compliment to
mankind involved in this issue: in spite of all their
irrationalities, inconsistencies, hypocrisies and evasions, the
majority of men will not act, in major issues, without a sense of
being morally right and will not oppose the morality they
have accepted. They will break it, they will cheat on it, but they
will not oppose it; and when they break it, they take the blame on
themselves. The power of morality is the greatest of all
intellectual powers—and mankind’s tragedy lies in the fact that the
vicious moral code men have accepted destroys them by means of the
best within them.
So long as altruism was their moral ideal, men had
to regard capitalism as immoral; capitalism certainly does not and
cannot work on the principle of selfless service and sacrifice.
This was the reason why the majority of the nineteenth-century
intellectuals regarded capitalism as a vulgar, uninspiring,
materialistic necessity of this earth, and continued to long for
their unearthly moral ideal. From the start, while capitalism was
creating the splendor of its achievements, creating it in silence,
unacknowledged and undefended (morally undefended), the
intellectuals were moving in greater and greater numbers towards a
new dream: socialism.
Just as a small illustration of how ineffectual a
defense of capitalism was offered by its most famous advocates, let
me mention that the British socialists, the Fabians, were
predominantly students and admirers of John Stuart Mill and Jeremy
Bentham.
The socialists had a certain kind of logic on their
side: if the collective sacrifice of all to all is the moral
ideal, then they wanted to establish this ideal in practice, here
and on this earth. The arguments that socialism would not and could
not work, did not stop them: neither has altruism ever worked, but
this has not caused men to stop and question it. Only reason
can ask such questions—and reason, they were told on all
sides, has nothing to do with morality, morality lies outside the
realm of reason, no rational morality can ever be
defined.
The fallacies and contradictions in the economic
theories of socialism were exposed and refuted time and time again,
in the nineteenth century as well as today. This did not and does
not stop anyone: it is not an issue of economics, but of morality.
The intellectuals and the so-called idealists were determined to
make socialism work. How? By that magic means of all
irrationalists: somehow.
It was not the tycoons of big business, it was not
the labor unions, it was not the working classes, it was the
intellectuals who reversed the trend toward political freedom and
revived the doctrines of the absolute State, of totalitarian
government rule, of the government’s right to control the lives of
the citizens in any manner it pleases. This time, it was not in the
name of the “divine right of kings,” but in the name of the divine
right of the masses. The basic principle was the same: the right to
enforce at the point of a gun the moral doctrines of whoever
happens to seize control of the machinery of government.
There are only two means by which men can deal with
one another: guns or logic. Force or persuasion. Those who know
that they cannot win by means of logic, have always resorted to
guns.
Well, ladies and gentlemen, the socialists got
their dream. They got it in the twentieth century and they got it
in triplicate, plus a great many lesser carbon copies; they got it
in every possible form and variant, so that now there can be no
mistake about its nature: Soviet Russia—Nazi Germany—Socialist
England.
This was the collapse of the modern
intellectuals’ most cherished tradition. It was World War II that
destroyed collectivism as a political ideal. Oh, yes, people still
mouth its slogans, by routine, by social conformity and by
default—but it is not a moral crusade any longer. It is an
ugly, horrifying reality—and part of the modern intellectuals’
guilt is the knowledge that they have created it. They have
seen for themselves the bloody slaughterhouse which they had once
greeted as a noble experiment—Soviet Russia. They have seen Nazi
Germany—and they know that “Nazi” means “National Socialism.”
Perhaps the worst blow to them, the greatest disillusionment, was
Socialist England: here was their literal dream, a bloodless
socialism, where force was not used for murder, only for
expropriation, where lives were not taken, only the products, the
meaning and the future of lives, here was a country that had not
been murdered, but had voted itself into suicide. Most of the
modern intellectuals, even the more evasive ones, have now
understood what socialism—or any form of political and economic
collectivism—actually means.
Today, their perfunctory advocacy of collectivism
is as feeble, futile and evasive as the alleged conservatives’
defense of capitalism. The fire and the moral fervor have gone out
of it. And when you hear the liberals mumble that Russia is not
really socialistic, or that it was all Stalin’s fault, or
that socialism never had a real chance in England, or that
what they advocate is something that’s different
somehow—you know that you are hearing the voices of men who
haven’t a leg to stand on, men who are reduced to some vague hope
that “somehow, my gang would have done it better.”
The secret dread of modern intellectuals, liberals
and conservatives alike, the unadmitted terror at the root of their
anxiety, which all of their current irrationalities are intended to
stave off and to disguise, is the unstated knowledge that Soviet
Russia is the full, actual, literal, consistent embodiment of the
morality of altruism, that Stalin did not corrupt a noble
ideal, that this is the only way altruism has to be or can ever be
practiced. If service and self-sacrifice are a moral ideal, and if
the “selfishness” of human nature prevents men from leaping into
sacrificial furnaces, there is no reason—no reason that a mystic
moralist could name—why a dictator should not push them in at the
point of bayonets—for their own good, or the good of humanity, or
the good of posterity, or the good of the latest bureaucrat’s
latest five-year plan. There is no reason that they can name to
oppose any atrocity. The value of a man’s life? His right to
exist? His right to pursue his own happiness? These are concepts
that belong to individualism and capitalism—to the antithesis of
the altruist morality.
Twenty years ago, the conservatives were uncertain,
evasive, morally disarmed before the aggressive moral
self-righteousness of the liberals. Today, both are
uncertain, evasive, morally disarmed before the aggressiveness of
the communists. It is not a moral aggressiveness any longer,
it is the plain aggressiveness of a thug—but what disarms the
modern intellectuals is the secret realization that a thug
is the inevitable, ultimate and only product of their
cherished morality.
I have said that faith and force are corollaries,
and that mysticism will always lead to the rule of brutality. The
cause of it is contained in the very nature of mysticism.
Reason is the only objective means of communication
and of understanding among men; when men deal with one another by
means of reason, reality is their objective standard and
frame of reference. But when men claim to possess supernatural
means of knowledge, no persuasion, communication or understanding
are possible. Why do we kill wild animals in the jungle? Because no
other way of dealing with them is open to us. And that is
the state to which mysticism reduces mankind—a state where, in case
of disagreement, men have no recourse except to physical violence.
And more: no man or mystical elite can hold a whole society
subjugated to their arbitrary assertions, edicts and whims, without
the use of force. Anyone who resorts to the formula: “It’s so,
because I say so,” will have to reach for a gun, sooner or later.
Communists, like all materialists, are neo-mystics: it does not
matter whether one rejects the mind in favor of revelations or in
favor of conditioned reflexes. The basic premise and the results
are the same.
Such is the nature of the evil which modern
intellectuals have helped to let loose in the world—and such is the
nature of their guilt.
Now take a look at the state of the world. The
signs and symptoms of the Dark Ages are rising again all over the
earth. Slave labor, executions without trial, torture chambers,
concentration camps, mass slaughter—all the things which the
capitalism of the nineteenth century had abolished in the civilized
world, are now brought back by the rule of the neo-mystics.
Look at the state of our intellectual life. In
philosophy, the climax of the Kantian version of reason has brought
us to the point where alleged philosophers, forgetting the
existence of dictionaries and grammar primers, run around studying
such questions as: “What do we mean when we say ‘The cat is on the
mat’?”—while other philosophers proclaim that nouns are an
illusion, but such terms as “if-then,” “but” and “or” have profound
philosophical significance—while still others toy with the idea of
an “index of prohibited words” and desire to place on it such words
as—I quote—“entity—essence—mind—matter—reality—thing.”
In psychology, one school holds that man, by
nature, is a helpless, guilt-ridden, instinct-driven
automaton—while another school objects that this is not true,
because there is no scientific evidence to prove that man is
conscious.
In literature, man is presented as a mindless
cripple, inhabiting garbage cans. In art, people announce that they
do not paint objects, they paint emotions. In youth
movements—if that’s what it can be called—young men attract
attention by openly announcing that they are “beat.”
The spirit of it all, both the cause of it and the
final climax, is contained in a quotation which I am going to read
to you. I will preface it by saying that in Atlas Shrugged I
stated that the world is being destroyed by mysticism and altruism,
which are anti-man, anti-mind and anti-life. You have undoubtedly
heard me being accused of exaggeration. I shall now read to you an
excerpt from the paper of a professor, published by an alumni
faculty seminar of a prominent university.
“Perhaps in the future reason will cease to be
important. Perhaps for guidance in time of trouble, people will
turn not to human thought, but to the human capacity for suffering.
Not the universities with their thinkers, but the places and people
in distress, the inmates of asylums and concentration camps, the
helpless decision makers in bureaucracy and the helpless soldiers
in foxholes—these will be the ones to lighten man’s way, to
refashion his knowledge of disaster into something creative. We may
be entering a new age. Our heroes may not be intellectual giants
like Isaac Newton or Albert Einstein, but victims like Anne Frank,
who will show us a greater miracle than thought. They will teach us
how to endure—how to create good in the midst of evil and how to
nurture love in the presence of death. Should this happen, however,
the university will still have its place. Even the intellectual man
can be an example of creative suffering.”
Observe that we are not to question “the helpless
decision makers in bureaucracy”—we are not to discover that
they are the cause of the concentration camps, of the
foxholes and of victims like Anne Frank—we are not to help such
victims, we are merely to feel suffering and to learn to suffer
some more—we can’t help it, the helpless bureaucrats can’t help it,
nobody can help it—the inmates of asylums will guide us, not
intellectual giants—suffering is the supreme value, not
reason.
This, ladies and gentlemen, is cultural
bankruptcy.
Since “challenge” is your slogan, I will say
that if you are looking for a challenge, you are facing the
greatest one in history. A moral revolution is the most
difficult, the most demanding, the most radical form of rebellion,
but that is the task to be done today, if you choose to accept it.
When I say “radical,” I mean it in its literal and reputable sense:
fundamental. Civilization does not have to perish. The brutes are
winning only by default. But in order to fight them to the finish
and with full rectitude, it is the altruist morality that you have
to reject.
Now, if you want to know what my philosophy,
Objectivism, offers you—I will give you a brief indication. I will
not attempt, in one lecture, to present my whole philosophy. I will
merely indicate to you what I mean by a rational morality of
self-interest, what I mean by the opposite of altruism, what kind
of morality is possible to man and why. I will preface it by
reminding you that most philosophers—especially most of them
today—have always claimed that morality is outside the province of
reason, that no rational morality can be defined, and that man has
no practical need of morality. Morality, they claim, is not
a necessity of man’s existence, but only some sort of mystical
luxury or arbitrary social whim; in fact, they claim, nobody can
prove why we should be moral at all; in reason, they claim, there’s
no reason to be moral.
I cannot summarize for you the essence and the base
of my morality any better than I did it in Atlas Shrugged.
So, rather than attempt to paraphrase it, I will read to you the
passages from Atlas Shrugged which pertain to the nature,
the base and the proof of my morality.
“Man’s mind is his basic tool of survival. Life is
given to him, survival is not. His body is given to him, its
sustenance is not. His mind is given to him, its content is not. To
remain alive, he must act, and before he can act he must know the
nature and purpose of his action. He cannot obtain his food without
a knowledge of food and of the way to obtain it. He cannot dig a
ditch—or build a cyclotron—without a knowledge of his aim and of
the means to achieve it. To remain alive, he must think.
“But to think is an act of choice. The key to what
you so recklessly call ‘human nature,’ the open secret you live
with, yet dread to name, is the fact that man is a being of
volitional consciousness. Reason does not work automatically;
thinking is not a mechanical process; the connections of logic are
not made by instinct. The function of your stomach, lungs or heart
is automatic; the function of your mind is not. In any hour and
issue of your life, you are free to think or to evade that effort.
But you are not free to escape from your nature, from the fact that
reason is your means of survival—so that for you, who
are a human being, the question ‘to be or not to be’ is the
question ‘to think or not to think.’
“A being of volitional consciousness has no
automatic course of behavior. He needs a code of values to guide
his actions. ‘Value’ is that which one acts to gain and keep,
‘virtue’ is the action by which one gains and keeps it. ‘Value’
presupposes an answer to the question: of value to whom and for
what? ‘Value’ presupposes a standard, a purpose and the necessity
of action in the face of an alternative. Where there are no
alternatives, no values are possible.
“There is only one fundamental alternative in the
universe: existence or non-existence—and it pertains to a single
class of entities: to living organisms. The existence of inanimate
matter is unconditional, the existence of life is not: it depends
on a specific course of action. Matter is indestructible, it
changes its forms, but it cannot cease to exist. It is only a
living organism that faces a constant alternative: the issue of
life or death. Life is a process of self-sustaining and
self-generated action. If an organism fails in that action, it
dies; its chemical elements remain, but its life goes out of
existence. It is only the concept of ‘Life’ that makes the concept
of ‘Value’ possible. It is only to a living entity that things can
be good or evil.
“A plant must feed itself in order to live; the
sunlight, the water, the chemicals it needs are the values its
nature has set it to pursue; its life is the standard of value
directing its actions. But a plant has no choice of action; there
are alternatives in the conditions it encounters, but there is no
alternative in its function: it acts automatically to further its
life, it cannot act for its own destruction.
“An animal is equipped for sustaining its life; its
senses provide it with an automatic code of action, an automatic
knowledge of what is good for it or evil. It has no power to extend
its knowledge or to evade it. In conditions where its knowledge
proves inadequate, it dies. But so long as it lives, it acts on its
knowledge, with automatic safety and no power of choice, it is
unable to ignore its own good, unable to decide to choose the evil
and act as its own destroyer.
“Man has no automatic code of survival. His
particular distinction from all other living species is the
necessity to act in the face of alternatives by means of
volitional choice. He has no automatic knowledge of what is
good for him or evil, what values his life depends on, what course
of action it requires. Are you prattling about an instinct of
self-preservation? An instinct of self-preservation is
precisely what man does not possess. An ‘instinct’ is an unerring
and automatic form of knowledge. A desire is not an instinct. A
desire to live does not give you the knowledge required for living.
And even man’s desire to live is not automatic: your secret evil
today is that that is the desire you do not hold. Your fear
of death is not a love for life and will not give you the knowledge
needed to keep it. Man must obtain his knowledge and choose his
actions by a process of thinking, which nature will not force him
to perform. Man has the power to act as his own destroyer—and that
is the way he has acted through most of his history. . . .
“Man has been called a rational being, but
rationality is a matter of choice—and the alternative his nature
offers him is: rational being or suicidal animal. Man has to be
man—by choice; he has to hold his life as a value—by choice; he has
to learn to sustain it—by choice; he has to discover the values it
requires and practice his virtues—by choice.
“A code of values accepted by choice is a code of
morality.
“Whoever you are, you who are hearing me now, I am
speaking to whatever living remnant is left uncorrupted within you,
to the remnant of the human, to your mind, and I say: There
is a morality of reason, a morality proper to man, and
Man’s Life is its standard of value.
“All that which is proper to the life of a rational
being is the good; all that which destroys it is the evil.
“Man’s life, as required by his nature, is not the
life of a mindless brute, of a looting thug or a mooching mystic,
but the life of a thinking being—not life by means of force or
fraud, but life by means of achievement—not survival at any price,
since there’s only one price that pays for man’s survival:
reason.
“Man’s life is the standard of morality, but
your own life is its purpose. If existence on earth is your
goal, you must choose your actions and values by the standard of
that which is proper to man—for the purpose of preserving,
fulfilling and enjoying the irreplaceable value which is your
life.”
This, ladies and gentlemen, is what Objectivism
offers you.
And when you make your choice, I would like you to
remember that the only alternative to it is communist slavery. The
“middle-of-the-road” is like an unstable, radioactive element that
can last only so long—and its time is running out. There is no more
chance for a middle-of-the-road.
The issue will be decided, not in the middle, but
between the two consistent extremes. It’s Objectivism or communism.
It’s a rational morality based on man’s right to exist—or altruism,
which means: slave labor camps under the rule of such masters as
you might have seen on the screens of your TV last year. If that is
what you prefer, the choice is yours.
But don’t make that choice blindly. You, the young
generation, have been betrayed in the most dreadful way by your
elders—by those liberals of the thirties who armed Soviet Russia,
and destroyed the last remnants of American capitalism. All that
they have to offer you now is foxholes, or the kind of attitude
expressed in the quotation on “creative suffering” that I read to
you. This is all that you will hear on any side: “Give up before
you have started. Give up before you have tried.” And to make sure
that you give up, they do not even let you know what the nineteenth
century was. I hope this may not be fully true here, but I have met
too many young people in universities, who have no clear idea, not
even in the most primitive terms, of what capitalism really is.
They do not let you know what the theory of capitalism is, nor how
it worked in practice, nor what was its actual history.
Don’t give up too easily; don’t sell out your life.
If you make an effort to inquire on your own, you will find that it
is not necessary to give up and that the allegedly powerful monster
now threatening us will run like a rat at the first sign of a human
step.
It is not physical danger that threatens you, and
it is not military considerations that make our so-called
intellectual leaders tell you that we are doomed. That is merely
their rationalization. The real danger is that communism is an
enemy whom they do not dare to fight on moral grounds, and it can
be fought only on moral grounds.
This, then, is the choice. Think it over. Consider
the subject, check your premises, check past history and find out
whether it is true that men can never be free. It isn’t true,
because they have been. Find out what made it possible. See for
yourself. And then if you are convinced—rationally convinced—then
let us save the world together. We still have time.
To quote Galt once more, such is the choice before
you. Let your mind and your love of existence decide.