Moxon’s Master
“Are you serious?—do you really believe that a
machine thinks?”
I got no immediate reply; Moxon was apparently
intent upon the coals in the grate, touching them deftly here and
there with the fire-poker till they signified a sense of his
attention by a brighter glow. For several weeks I had been
observing in him a growing habit of delay in answering even the
most trivial of commonplace questions. His air, however, was that
of preoccupation rather than deliberation: one might have said that
he had “something on his mind.”
Presently he said:
“What is a ‘machine’? The word has been variously
defined. Here is one definition from a popular dictionary: ‘Any
instrument or organization by which power is applied and made
effective, or a desired effect produced.’ Well, then, is not a man
a machine? And you will admit that he thinks—or thinks he
thinks.”
“If you do not wish to answer my question,” I said,
rather testily, “why not say so?—all that you say is mere evasion.
You know well enough that when I say ‘machine’ I do not mean a man,
but something that man has made and controls.”
“When it does not control him,” he said, rising
abruptly and looking out of a window, whence nothing was visible in
the blackness of a stormy night. A moment later he turned about and
with a smile said: “I beg your pardon; I had no thought of evasion.
I considered the dictionary man’s unconscious testimony suggestive
and worth something in the discussion. I can give your question a
direct answer easily enough: I do believe that a machine thinks
about the work that it is doing.”
That was direct enough, certainly. It was not
altogether pleasing, for it tended to confirm a sad suspicion that
Moxon’s devotion to study and work in his machine-shop had not been
good for him. I knew, for one thing, that he suffered from
insomnia, and that is no light affliction. Had it affected his
mind? His reply to my question seemed to me then evidence that it
had; perhaps I should think differently about it now. I was younger
then, and among the blessings that are not denied to youth is
ignorance. Incited by that great stimulant to controversy, I
said:
“And what, pray, does it think with—in the absence
of a brain?”
The reply, coming with less than his customary
delay, took his favorite form of counter-interrogation:
“With what does a plant think—in the absence of a
brain?”
“Ah, plants also belong to the philosopher class! I
should be pleased to know some of their conclusions; you may omit
the premises.”
“Perhaps,” he replied, apparently unaffected by my
foolish irony, “you may be able to infer their convictions from
their acts. I will spare you the familiar examples of the sensitive
mimosa, the several insectivorous flowers and those whose stamens
bend down and shake their pollen upon the entering bee in order
that he may fertilize their distant mates. But observe this. In an
open spot in my garden I planted a climbing vine. When it was
barely above the surface I set a stake into the soil a yard away.
The vine at once made for it, but as it was about to reach it after
several days I removed it a few feet. The vine at once altered its
course, making an acute angle, and again made for the stake. This
manœuvre was repeated several times but finally, as if discouraged,
the vine abandoned the pursuit and ignoring further attempts to
divert it traveled to a small tree, further away, which it
climbed.
“Roots of the eucalyptus will prolong themselves
incredibly in search of moisture. A well-known horticulturist
relates that one entered an old drain pipe and followed it until it
came to a break, where a section of the pipe had been removed to
make way for a stone wall that had been built across its course.
The root left the drain and followed the wall until it found an
opening where a stone had fallen out. It crept through and
following the other side of the wall back to the drain, entered the
unexplored part and resumed its journey.”
“And all this?”
“Can you miss the significance of it? It shows the
consciousness of plants. It proves that they think.”
“Even if it did—what then? We were speaking, not of
plants, but of machines. They may be composed partly of wood—wood
that has no longer vitality—or wholly of metal. Is thought an
attribute also of the mineral kingdom?”
“How else do you explain the phenomena, for
example, of crystallization?”
“I do not explain them.”
“Because you cannot without affirming what you wish
to deny, namely, intelligent cooperation among the constituent
elements of the crystals. When soldiers form lines, or hollow
squares, you call it reason. When wild geese in flight take the
form of a letter V you say instinct. When the homogeneous atoms of
a mineral, moving freely in solution arrange themselves into shapes
mathematically perfect, or particles of frozen moisture into the
symmetrical and beautiful forms of snowflakes, you have nothing to
say. You have not even invented a name to conceal your heroic
unreason.”
Moxon was speaking with unusual animation and
earnestness. As he paused I heard in an adjoining room known to me
as his “machine-shop,” which no one but himself was permitted to
enter, a singular thumping sound, as of some one pounding upon a
table with an open hand. Moxon heard it at the same moment and,
visibly agitated, rose and hurriedly passed into the room whence it
came. I thought it odd that any one else should be in there, and my
interest in my friend—with doubtless a touch of unwarrantable
curiosity—led me to listen intently, though, I am happy to say, not
at the keyhole. There were confused sounds, as of a struggle or
scuffle; the floor shook. I distinctly heard hard breathing and a
hoarse whisper which said “Damn you!” Then all was silent, and
presently Moxon reappeared and said, with a rather sorry
smile:
“Pardon me for leaving you so abruptly. I have a
machine in there that lost its temper and cut up rough.”
Fixing my eyes steadily upon his left cheek which
was traversed by four parallel excoriations showing blood, I
said:
“How would it do to trim its nails?”
I could have spared myself the jest; he gave it no
attention, but seated himself in the chair that he had left and
resumed the interrupted monologue as if nothing had occurred:
“Doubtless you do not hold with those (I need not
name them to a man of your reading) who have taught that all matter
is sentient, that every atom is a living, feeling, conscious being.
I do. There is no such thing as dead, inert matter; it is
all alive; all instinct with force, actual and potential; all
sensitive to the same forces in its environment and susceptible to
the contagion of higher and subtler ones residing in such superior
organisms as it may be brought into relation with, as those of man
when he is fashioning it into an instrument of his will. It absorbs
something of his intelligence and purpose—more of them in
proportion to the complexity of the resulting machine and that of
its work.
“Do you happen to recall Herbert Spencer’s
definition of ‘Life’?42 I read it thirty years ago. He
may have altered it afterward, for anything I know, but in all that
time I have been unable to think of a single word that could
profitably be changed or added or removed. It seems to me not only
the best definition, but the only possible one.
“ ‘Life,’ he says, ‘is a definite combination of
heterogeneous changes, both simultaneous and successive, in
correspondence with external coexistences and sequences.’ ”
“That defines the phenomenon,” I said, “but gives
no hint of its cause.”
“That,” he replied, is all that any definition can
do. As Mill43 points out, we know nothing of cause
except as an antecedent—nothing of effect except as a consequent.
Of certain phenomena, one never occurs without another, which is
dissimilar: the first in point of time we call cause, the second,
effect. One who had many times seen a rabbit pursued by a dog, and
had never seen rabbits and dogs otherwise, would think the rabbit
the cause of the dog.
“But I fear,” he added, laughing naturally enough,
“that my rabbit is leading me a long way from the track of my
legitimate quarry: I’m indulging in the pleasure of the chase for
its own sake. What I want you to observe is that in Herbert
Spencer’s definition of ‘life’ the activity of a machine is
included—there is nothing in the definition that is not applicable
to it. According to this sharpest of observers and deepest of
thinkers, if a man during his period of activity is alive, so is a
machine when in operation. As an inventor and constructor of
machines I know that to be true.”
Moxon was silent for a long time, gazing absently
into the fire. It was growing late and I thought it time to be
going, but somehow I did not like the notion of leaving him in that
isolated house, all alone except for the presence of some person of
whose nature my conjectures could go no further than that it was
unfriendly, perhaps malign. Leaning toward him and looking
earnestly into his eyes while making a motion with my hand through
the door of his workshop, I said:
“Moxon, whom have you in there?”
Somewhat to my surprise he laughed lightly and
answered without hesitation:
“Nobody; the incident that you have in mind was
caused by my folly in leaving a machine in action with nothing to
act upon, while I undertook the interminable task of enlightening
your understanding. Do you happen to know that Consciousness is the
creature of Rhythm?”
“O bother them both!” I replied, rising and laying
hold of my overcoat. “I’m going to wish you good night; and I’ll
add the hope that the machine which you inadvertently left in
action will have her gloves on the next time you think it needful
to stop her.”
Without waiting to observe the effect of my shot I
left the house.
Rain was falling, and the darkness was intense. In
the sky beyond the crest of a hill toward which I groped my way
along precarious plank sidewalks and across miry, unpaved streets I
could see the faint glow of the city’s lights, but behind me
nothing was visible but a single window of Moxon’s house. It glowed
with what seemed to me a mysterious and fateful meaning. I knew it
was an uncurtained aperture in my friend’s “machine-shop,” and I
had little doubt that he had resumed the studies interrupted by his
duties as my instructor in mechanical consciousness and the
fatherhood of Rhythm. Odd, and in some degree humorous, as his
convictions seemed to me at that time, I could not wholly divest
myself of the feeling that they had some tragic relation to his
life and character—perhaps to his destiny—although I no longer
entertained the notion that they were the vagaries of a disordered
mind. Whatever might be thought of his views, his exposition of
them was too logical for that. Over and over, his last words came
back to me: “Consciousness is the creature of Rhythm.” Bald and
terse as the statement was, I now found it infinitely alluring. At
each recurrence it broadened in meaning and deepened in suggestion.
Why, here, (I thought) is something upon which to found a
philosophy. If consciousness is the product of rhythm all things
are conscious, for all have motion, and all motion is
rhythmic. I wondered if Moxon knew the significance and breadth of
his thought—the scope of this momentous generalization, or had he
arrived at his philosophic faith by the tortuous and uncertain road
of observation?
That faith was then new to me, and all Moxon’s
expounding had failed to make me a convert; but now it seemed as if
a great light shone about me, like that which fell upon Saul of
Tarsus;44 and out there in the storm and darkness and
solitude I experienced what Lewes45 calls “The endless
variety and excitement of philosophic thought.” I exulted in a new
sense of knowledge, a new pride of reason. My feet seemed hardly to
touch the earth; it was as if I were uplifted and borne through the
air by invisible wings.
Yielding to an impulse to seek further light from
him whom I now recognized as my master and guide, I had
unconsciously turned about, and almost before I was aware of having
done so found myself again at Moxon’s door. I was drenched with
rain, but felt no discomfort. Unable in my excitement to find the
doorbell I instinctively tried the knob. It turned and, entering, I
mounted the stairs to the room that I had so recently left. All was
dark and silent; Moxon, as I had supposed, was in the adjoining
room—the “machine-shop.” Groping along the wall until I found the
communicating door I knocked loudly several times, but got no
response, which I attributed to the uproar outside, for the wind
was blowing a gale and dashing the rain against the thin walls in
sheets. The drumming upon the shingle roof spanning the unceiled
room was loud and incessant.
I had never been invited into the machine-shop—had,
indeed, been denied admittance, as had all others, with one
exception, a skilled metal worker, of whom no one knew anything
except that his name was Haley and his habit silence. But in my
spiritual exaltation, discretion and civility were alike forgotten
and I opened the door. What I saw took all philosophical
speculation out of me in short order.
Moxon sat facing me at the farther side of a small
table upon which a single candle made all the light that was in the
room. Opposite him, his back toward me, sat another person. On the
table between the two was a chess-board; the men were playing. I
knew little of chess, but as only a few pieces were on the board it
was obvious that the game was near its close. Moxon was intensely
interested—not so much, it seemed to me, in the game as in his
antagonist, upon whom he had fixed so intent a look that, standing
though I did directly in the line of his vision, I was altogether
unobserved. His face was ghastly white, and his eyes glittered like
diamonds. Of his antagonist I had only a back view, but that was
sufficient; I should not have cared to see his face.
He was apparently not more than five feet in
height, with proportions suggesting those of a gorilla—a tremendous
breadth of shoulders, thick, short neck and broad, squat head,
which had a tangled growth of black hair and was topped with a
crimson fez. A tunic of the same color, belted tightly to the
waist, reached the seat—apparently a box—upon which he sat; his
legs and feet were not seen. His left forearm appeared to rest in
his lap; he moved his pieces with his right hand, which seemed
disproportionately long.
I had shrunk back and now stood a little to one
side of the doorway and in shadow. If Moxon had looked farther than
the face of his opponent he could have observed nothing now, except
that the door was open. Something forbade me either to enter or to
retire, a feeling—I know not how it came—that I was in the presence
of an imminent tragedy and might serve my friend by remaining. With
a scarcely conscious rebellion against the indelicacy of the act I
remained.
The play was rapid. Moxon hardly glanced at the
board before making his moves, and to my unskilled eye seemed to
move the piece most convenient to his hand, his motions in doing so
being quick, nervous and lacking in precision. The response of his
antagonist, while equally prompt in the inception, was made with a
slow, uniform, mechanical and, I thought, somewhat theatrical
movement of the arm, that was a sore trial to my patience. There
was something unearthly about it all, and I caught myself
shuddering. But I was wet and cold.
Two or three times after moving a piece the
stranger slightly inclined his head, and each time I observed that
Moxon shifted his king. All at once the thought came to me that the
man was dumb. And then that he was a machine—an automaton
chess-player! Then I remembered that Moxon had once spoken to me of
having invented such a piece of mechanism, though I did not
understand that it had actually been constructed. Was all his talk
about the consciousness and intelligence of machines merely a
prelude to eventual exhibition of this device—only a trick to
intensify the effect of its mechanical action upon me in my
ignorance of its secret?
A fine end, this, of all my intellectual
transports—my “endless variety and excitement of philosophic
thought!” I was about to retire in disgust when something occurred
to hold my curiosity. I observed a shrug of the thing’s great
shoulders, as if it were irritated: and so natural was this—so
entirely human—that in my new view of the matter it startled me.
Nor was that all, for a moment later it struck the table sharply
with its clenched hand. At that gesture Moxon seemed even more
startled than I: he pushed his chair a little backward, as in
alarm.
Presently Moxon, whose play it was, raised his hand
high above the board, pounced upon one of his pieces like a
sparrow-hawk and with the exclamation “checkmate!” rose quickly to
his feet and stepped behind his chair. The automaton sat
motionless.
The wind had now gone down, but I heard, at
lessening intervals and progressively louder, the rumble and roll
of thunder. In the pauses between I now became conscious of a low
humming or buzzing which, like the thunder, grew momentarily louder
and more distinct. It seemed to come from the body of the
automaton, and was unmistakably a whirring of wheels. It gave me
the impression of a disordered mechanism which had escaped the
repressive and regulating action of some controlling part—an effect
such as might be expected if a pawl46 should be jostled
from the teeth of a ratchet-wheel. But before I had time for much
conjecture as to its nature my attention was taken by the strange
motions of the automaton itself. A slight but continuous convulsion
appeared to have possession of it. In body and head it shook like a
man with palsy or an ague chill, and the motion augmented every
moment until the entire figure was in violent agitation. Suddenly
it sprang to its feet and with a movement almost too quick for the
eye to follow shot forward across table and chair, with both arms
thrust forth to their full length—the posture and lunge of a diver.
Moxon tried to throw himself backward out of reach, but he was too
late: I saw the horrible thing’s hands close upon his throat, his
own clutch its wrists. Then the table was overturned, the candle
thrown to the floor and extinguished, and all was black dark. But
the noise of the struggle was dreadfully distinct, and most
terrible of all were the raucous, squawking sounds made by the
strangled man’s efforts to breathe. Guided by the infernal hubbub,
I sprang to the rescue of my friend, but had hardly taken a stride
in the darkness when the whole room blazed with a blinding white
light that burned into my brain and heart and memory a vivid
picture of the combatants on the floor, Moxon underneath, his
throat still in the clutch of those iron hands, his head forced
backward, his eyes protruding, his mouth wide open and his tongue
thrust out; and—horrible contrast!—upon the painted face of his
assassin an expression of tranquil and profound thought, as in the
solution of a problem in chess! This I observed, then all was
blackness and silence.
Three days later I recovered consciousness in a
hospital. As the memory of that tragic night slowly evolved in my
ailing brain I recognized in my attendant Moxon’s confidential
workman, Haley. Responding to a look he approached, smiling.
“Tell me about it,” I managed to say, faintly—“all
about it.”
“Certainly,” he said; “you were carried unconscious
from a burning house—Moxon’s. Nobody knows how you came to be
there. You may have to do a little explaining. The origin of the
fire is a bit mysterious, too. My own notion is that the house was
struck by lightning.”
“And Moxon?”
“Buried yesterday—what was left of him.”
Apparently this reticent person could unfold
himself on occasion. When imparting shocking intelligence to the
sick he was affable enough. After some moments of the keenest
mental suffering I ventured to ask another question:
“Who rescued me?”
“Well, if that interests you—I did.”
“Thank you, Mr. Haley, and may God bless you for
it. Did you rescue, also, that charming product of your skill, the
automaton chess-player that murdered its inventor?”
The man was silent a long time, looking away from
me. Presently he turned and gravely said:
“Do you know that?”
“I do,” I replied; “I saw it done.”
That was many years ago. If asked to-day I should
answer less confidently.